Favoritism vs. Nondiscrimination?
In the April issue of First Things (“God and Bigotry at Yale,” Public Square), Richard John Neuhaus criticizes the Yale Law School’s decision not to exempt the Christian Legal Society (CLS) from the School’s general policy that all employers wishing to participate in the School’s on-campus interviewing process must sign a form stating that they do not discriminate on the basis of (among other things) religious belief.
Let me say at the start that I regard the question as a difficult and close one, and that I appreciate the good will with which Gregory Baylor, the assistant director of CLS, has pressed his case, despite our ultimate disagreement.
Mr. Baylor and I agree on two propositions. First, the Yale Law School is a secular institution whose own internal life is governed by a principle of religious nondiscrimination. The School does not hire faculty or admit students or distribute resources on the basis of religious belief. It would offend this principle, for example, if a faculty member advertising for a student teaching assistant stated that only Catholics (or Jews or Lutherans or Muslims) need apply. Similarly, it would offend the School’s principle of nondiscrimination if the Registrar were to announce that henceforth summer financial support was to be awarded only to students of certain religious faiths.
Second, CLS is a religious organization whose internal life is governed by a principle of religious favoritism. Nothing could be more obvious or less objectionable, and it would be as presumptuous for a secular organization, like the Yale Law School, to suggest that CLS should govern its own affairs by a principle of nondiscrimination as it would be for CLS to suggest that the internal life of the Yale Law School should be restructured so that adherents of one faith might be favored over those of any other.
The difficulty in this case arises because the Law School’s on-campus interviewing process straddles the line between its internal life (which the School is free to arrange as it chooses) and the life of other organizations—of the employers participating in the process—whose governing norms the School has no power, or desire, to challenge. If CLS makes arrangements on its own to interview our students, its dealings with them fall outside the boundaries of the School’s institutional life and are not subject to the School’s policy of nondiscrimination. But the Law School’s on-campus interviewing process is administered and subsidized by the School itself, and to that extent the special opportunities this process affords our students are opportunities the School provides. They are opportunities that arise within the orbit of the School’s own life, in the same way that opportunities to compete for teaching assistantships and summer financial support do, and it would therefore be as real a breach of the School’s internal ethic of nondiscrimination to permit religious favoritism in the distribution of these opportunities as it would be to permit it in the distribution of any other benefits the School provides.
I recognize that requiring CLS to honor the Yale Law School’s policy of religious nondiscrimination imposes a cost on CLS by making it more difficult for CLS to recruit our students. But exempting CLS from our policy would constitute a moral interference in the internal life of the Yale Law School, and that is a very real cost as well. I do not see a solution that will be costless to both institutions, and that of course is why the problem is so difficult. In the end, I must prefer the internal regulative norms of the institution I have pledged to protect, just as Mr. Baylor must prefer the internal norms of the institution he represents. This leaves us in disagreement, but I would hope that we can at least recognize and respect the moral imperatives to which each of us owes his allegiance.
Mr. Neuhaus’ essay makes a complex question appear overly simple, and invites readers to take sides rather than continue a conversation. I prefer to continue the conversation, which I believe a spirit of genuine civility requires.
In that conversation, there are many further questions that might be asked. Let me close by asking one: What must CLS be committed to before Mr. Baylor can say, in good faith, that his organization does not discriminate in the sense the Yale Law School’s policy forbids? Would it be enough to say, for example, that CLS is willing to interview students of all faiths, though it thinks it unlikely that any but professing Christians will be hired? A private law firm that states it will interview students of all races, but says it is unlikely that any black students will be hired, would not meet the Law School’s requirement of nondiscrimination. By contrast, if an organization devoted to the protection of religious freedom were to say that it was prepared to interview all students, the devout as well as nonbelievers, but thought it unlikely that any but those committed to the cause would be hired, it is my own view that this would not constitute discrimination of the kind the Law School’s policy forbids.
Which of these last two cases does the first one most resemble? Perhaps this question can be the basis for a further conversation.
Anthony T. Kronman, Dean
Yale Law School
Father Neuhaus replies:
On the contrary, Dean Kronman’s letter makes a simple question appear very complex. As I pointed out in “God and Bigotry at Yale,” the problem with YLS’s “principle of religious nondiscrimination” is that it discriminates against religious organizations in its interviewing process. It also discriminates against its own students who may want to interview with a group such as CLS. That double discrimination results from Dean Kronman’s failure to see that his idea of a “secular institution” is anything but neutral. Dean Kronman says, in effect, to CLS: We have our belief system and you have your belief system and we’re Yale Law School and you’re not, so that’s that. He calls for “further conversation” in “a spirit of genuine civility” while simultaneously declaring an “ultimate disagreement.” Since he has arrived at his conclusion, it is not clear what further conversation would be about.
“This leaves us in disagreement,” he writes, “but I would hope that we can at least recognize and respect the moral imperatives to which each of us owes his allegiance.” One can recognize what Dean Kronman takes to be a moral imperative to discriminate against religious persons and institutions, but one cannot respect it. And he obviously does not respect the moral imperatives to which CLS owes allegiance. Although apparently unaware of the insult, he says that CLS “is governed by a principle of religious favoritism.” Fulfilling one’s duty to God is not a matter of preference and recruiting others to that cause is not an exercise in “religious favoritism.” Even more egregiously, Dean Kronman introduces the example of a law firm that discriminates on the basis of race. Apparently Dean Kronman fails to appreciate that the comparison of religion with racism puts a severe strain on “a spirit of genuine civility.” It is to be feared that Dean Kronman has little understanding of, never mind respect for, the nature of religious commitment. He might consult his YLS colleague Stephen Carter who has written insightfully about the “trivialization” of religion. (I confess that I am puzzled by the silence of Mr. Carter to date, although he has been asked to address the problem of the exclusion of CLS.)
Dean Kronman’s references to distributing financial support and other benefits on the basis of religious faith is an embarrassingly obvious red herring. Nobody is proposing that; it has nothing to do with the present discussion; and, were it proposed, it would surely be opposed by almost everyone, including, I have no doubt, CLS. The question at hand is whether CLS and students who might want to interview with CLS should be granted the same access that is accorded others.
Dean Kronman talks about “interference” with the internal life of YLS. This, I am afraid, is entirely disingenuous. There is no symmetry whatever between the position of CLS and that of YLS. The former cannot in any way “interfere” with the law school. The decision not to discriminate against CLS and other religious organizations lies entirely with YLS. In its anti-discrimination laws, the U.S. Government regularly grants exemptions for religious institutions. Does Dean Kronman think this means religious institutions are “interfering” with the Government? Of course not. The Government, for very good reasons having to do with the distinctive nature of religion, decides to make an exception. Harvard Law School permits CLS to interview on campus. Does Dean Kronman think Harvard is guilty of practicing “religious favoritism”? Harvard has decided not to discriminate against religious institutions. Yale has decided, in the name of nondiscrimination, to discriminate against religious institutions.
Dean Kronman is wrong in suggesting that the problem is that YLS and CLS are equal parties operating by incompatible principles. Between the two, there is no equality of power or moral responsibility. CLS cannot and does not discriminate against Yale. If Yale decides to permit its students to interview with CLS in the same way that they can interview with other organizations, that is no compromise whatever of the ability of YLS to govern its internal life. It would simply mean that YLS, along with federal and state governments, other law schools, and most corporations, recognizes that decency, common sense, and justice preclude discrimination on the basis of religion. Only religious institutions may and must discriminate on the basis of religious commitment. As, mutatis mutandis, law schools may and must discriminate on the basis of commitment to law.
In other words, and contra Dean Kronman’s main argument, the problem is not created by the different purposes of YLS and CLS. They are very different institutions, but CLS has no complaint against YLS being what it is, except that YLS excludes it from the interviewing process. YLS does have a complaint against CLS, namely, that it is a religious institution. Yale will be no less self-governing if it decides to grant a religious exemption from its rules. Indeed, making such decisions is precisely the meaning of self-government. No decision at all is required on the part of CLS. It clearly wants to interview students at YLS. The question is whether it will be permitted to do so. The decision is Yale’s and Yale’s alone.
Finally, the last case proposed at the end of Dean Kronman’s letter should not go unremarked. Readers will want to judge for themselves, but as best I can make it out Dean Kronman is inviting CLS, as the price of admission to the interview process, to dissemble about its hiring practices. It is a troubling invitation coming from a law school dean who has written extensively about the ethical state of the professions. Troubling also is the implication that the protection of religious freedom is a partisan cause not shared by nonbelievers. Whatever YLS may decide about not discriminating against religious institutions, it does seem that further conversation is in order.
Well Worth an Argument
In the April issue of First Things (“Religion Within the Limits of Morality Alone,” Public Square), Richard John Neuhaus says that my article “Writing History in a World Without Ends” (Pro Ecclesia, Fall 1996) is “well worth an argument.” In setting forth his part of the argument, Father Neuhaus contends that my comments on the U.S. Catholic bishops’ neutrality as regards slavery in the antebellum era “egregiously and... smugly imposes contemporary moral criteria upon the past.” This imposition, he says, is driven by an ecclesiology that is limited by morality, to the neglect of several other dimensions of Church life, such as “revealed truth, dogma, ordered ministry, sacramental bonds, and diverse traditions of discipleship.” Calling for “a doctrine of the Church that rests on more than the one pillar of ethics,” Neuhaus admonishes me by noting that “the Church is constituted more by mystery than by morality.”
The crux of the problem, he goes on to argue (drawing on a critique of feminist theology by R. R. Reno that appeared in the same issue of Pro Ecclesia as my article), is that I am captured by a modern, post-Kantian paradigm that puts forth an “ecclesiology within the limits of morality alone.” After conceding that “philosophically and theologically” I am “light years away from Kant,” Neuhaus still finds enough problems in my article to warrant this indictment: “Baxter, like Elizabeth Johnson and Rosemary Radford Ruether, is a child of Kant, a modern theologian who critiques the entirety of the tradition by a criterion of his own choosing.”
Neuhaus’ critique is also “well worth an argument,” so for the sake of argument, I offer the following three responses.
First, my article is directed primarily not at the antebellum Catholic bishops and their neutrality on slavery, but rather at John Tracy Ellis’ account of their neutrality, an account that was first set forth in 1955 and then revised in 1969. Although this would still qualify as an instance of imposing moral standards upon the past, it is a past that is rather recent; so recent a past, indeed, that it weighs very heavily on the present, for, as I show in my article, Ellis’ narrative, and the faith/politics autonomy that controls it, still shapes the present-day writing of U.S. Catholic history.
And yet, even to the extent that my article does cast judgment on the U.S. Catholic bishops of the antebellum era, it should be noted that their neutrality on slavery was judged and found wanting according to the moral criteria of their time by such prominent Catholics as Daniel O’Connell of Ireland, Monsignor Doupanloup of France, William Gaston of North Carolina, Father Claude Pascal Maistre of New Orleans, and Archbishop John Baptist Purcell of Cincinnati, who broke with his fellow bishops’ neutrality late in 1862. These people, who do not appear in Ellis’ history but who do appear in Cyprian Davis’ The History of Black Catholics in the United States, testify to the fact that at least some Catholics of the mid-nineteenth century found the moral resources to condemn the institution of slavery. My article suggests that we try to imagine an historical narrative whose plot line gives prominence to their stance rather than that of the U.S. Catholic bishops.
Second, my article is not, as Fr. Neuhaus claims, premised on a Kantian understanding of the relation between the Church and morality. Kant’s project was to free morality from tutelage to the authority and tradition of the Church by providing an account of the autonomy of morality grounded in reason qua reason. My article is part of an attempt to demonstrate the necessity of the Church for moral reflection, and the inextricable relation between ecclesial and moral discourse. If Fr. Neuhaus can show that Kant held there to be an inextricable connection between the Church and moral reasoning (and I doubt that he can), then I would readily acknowledge my identity as a child of Kant, in this limited sense.
But at the same time I would still point to another lineage in showing a connection between the Church and morality, a lineage stretching back to Moses and the prophets. In this tradition, the Church is constituted by mystery (Fr. Neuhaus is right about this), but the mystery centers on Christ’s redemption, which, as Pope John Paul II has explained in Veritatis Splendor, opens up for us “the possibility of realizing the entire truth of our being,” a realization that includes overcoming domination by concupiscence and enjoying the healing, restorative gift of the Holy Spirit. In this tradition, the Church is not held “within the limits of morality.” Rather, morality is expanded to include all aspects of church life.
This is why St. Paul exhorts his readers (in language at once liturgical, ecclesial, and moral) to present their bodies as a living sacrifice of praise and thus to live as members of the Body of Christ, teaching, preaching, giving alms, doing works of mercy, providing hospitality, repaying good for evil, and so on (Romans 12). This is also why Aquinas identifies the sacramental life of the Church as the means by which the virtues are formed and perfected. This is also why the Church excommunicated not only for doctrinal offenses such as Nestorianism and cultic offenses such as breaking the seal of the confessional, but also for moral offenses such as abortion. My point is this: there is no sphere of church life that is located in some sphere beyond morality, as Fr. Neuhaus implies, and you do not have to be a child of Kant to hold this view.
Third, Fr. Neuhaus is mistaken when he accuses me of criticizing “the entirety of the tradition.” My critique is not of “the entirety of the tradition,” but of only one tradition within the tradition, namely, the Americanist tradition. The confusion stems from the overall position that Fr. Neuhaus has been developing for years now, a position that merits the label “Americanist” inasmuch as it holds that “the entirety of the tradition” unequivocally endorses the political order established in the United States of America.
In good Americanist fashion, Fr. Neuhaus seems to think that the theology and political theory of Augustine and Aquinas automatically point ahead to the founding fathers and their Catholic supporters, John Carroll, John England, John Ireland, John Ryan, and John Courtney Murray, to name a few. If one dissents from this intellectual trajectory, he surmises, one must be drawing on “a criterion of [one’s] own choosing,” not on an alternative reading of the tradition. Thus Fr. Neuhaus never seriously faces the theoretical tension between justice grounded in true religion (Augustine) and the natural law (Aquinas) and the proceduralist notions of justice sponsored by the modern liberal state.
Nor does he face the practical tension between mores in the United States and the moral teaching of the Church. Instead, much like his hero John Courtney Murray, he continues to insist that there exists a fundamental harmony between Catholicism and the United States, all the while explaining away any friction in terms of recent cultural decline (hence his lament over “how far the disintegration of society has progressed in the past four decades”). Thus, whatever questions Neuhaus raises about the moral capacity of the United States to adhere to the natural law, as in the “crisis of democracy” forum sponsored in this journal, are purely reformist in character: the nation will get straightened out morally once we get our people onto the Supreme Court.
As I see it, the much celebrated “crisis of democracy” points to a deeper problem endemic to politics in a liberal society, the problem of generating a politics without substantive agreement on the ends to which political life is to be ordered. For Neuhaus, this problem can be solved by making politics a matter of means, and reserving the matter of ends to religion, which would then permeate the body politic. What he fails to consider is the extent to which the body politic can permeate religion and bleach out its distinctive character. When this happens, the Church ceases to respond critically to the political life of whatever nation in which it is located. It loses its shape and substance as a body and its members learn to tolerate practices such as slave trading and abortion—usually with the aid and comfort of theological formulations such as “the Church is constituted more by mystery than by morality.”
(The Rev.) Michael J. Baxter, C.S.C.
Department of Theology
University of Notre Dame
Notre Dame, IN
RJN replies:
Fr. Baxter’s position is well worth further argument, and I will get around to that in due course. For the moment, I simply state for the record that I do not believe the Catholic tradition “unequivocally endorses” the political order of the U.S. I emphatically reject such a view. As to other matters, more later.
A Confessional State?
When I was at Princeton last year, I read a draft of Father Michael J. Baxter’s article, “Writing History in a World Without Ends.” At that time, I expressed agreement with him that the temptation to Americanism was by no means a figment of the Roman curia’s imagination—either then or now. The large-scale collapse of faith and morality among American Catholics in the last generation proves that Rome was actually quite prescient about what could happen once the Catholic immigrants were assimilated.
Of course in the last century the assimilationists like Cardinal Gibbons and Archbishop Ireland were eager flag-wavers, and the anti-assimilationists were German Catholics who wanted to retain their own cultural identity and disliked the Irish bishops. The Americanizers responded that German particularism is potentially anti-Roman and can lose sight of Catholicity. Both sides made valid points, and Leo XIII responded appropriately in Testem Benevolentiae.
What I argued against Fr. Baxter is that he, too, is an Americanist in a more subtle way. I asked if he intended to take the position of Bishop Dupanloup and Montalembert in the last century: that the “thesis” or objectively best form of government would be a Catholic confessional state, but that in contemporary circumstances Catholics must accept the liberal state as a “hypothesis”—that is, as a tolerable situation necessary in order to avoid greater evils but not as a good thing in and of itself. Fr. Baxter hesitated to say this even though he knows well that John Courtney Murray’s critics (such as Cardinal Ottaviani, Msgr. Joseph Clifford Fenton, and Father Francis J. Connell, CSSR) did uphold this in the American Ecclesiastical Review. I told Fr. Baxter that unless he was willing to uphold in theory the thesis of the Catholic confessional state, his own accusations of Americanism would recoil on him.
I also suggested that Fr. Baxter’s pacifist politics owed more to American sectarian Protestant radicalism than to the Catholic tradition. When Fr. Baxter writes Catholic history as if it began and ended with Dorothy Day and the Catholic Worker Movement, he manifests an Americanist myopia more marked than any displayed by John Tracy Ellis, Jay P. Dolan, or David O’Brien. Fr. Baxter’s purportedly prophetic and evangelical alternative sounds typically American to me—the standard fare long since provided by the Quakers and other “peace churches” in their policy statements. What is so profound or prophetic about that?
As I understand Murray, he held that the thesis of the Catholic confessional state was not a necessary aspect of the Catholic doctrine of church and state, though the medieval and post-Tridentine Catholic states were defensible in their historical context. Fr. Murray’s critics held that he had conceded too much to the theory of the liberal state. Looking at the present American situation, I now think that we should uphold the thesis precisely in order to pursue the ideological critique and political engagement pioneered by John Courtney Murray.
If one realizes that the confessional state is not possible under present circumstances and that all Christian political involvement assumes that any political order is a “hypothesis” in relation to the Kingdom, it is possible to appreciate John Courtney Murray’s seminal work and yet avoid slipping by degrees into what Fr. Baxter calls a “world without ends.”
Ironically enough, this theoretical defense of the old thesis would serve a purpose in our dialogue/controversy with other groups who do not conform to liberal political assumptions: the Christian Reconstructionists (who criticize Abraham Kuyper in much the same way as Fenton criticized Murray;) Orthodox Jews in both Israel and the Diaspora, whose normative tradition has a problematic relation to the Israeli state and to the fact that it is not a Torah-state; and Muslims, whose religion in principle acknowledges no relative autonomy of the temporal sphere. Our mode of argument may be useful to them in their analogous political and religious reflection and action.
If Fr. Baxter is serious, then let him rise to the challenge of defending in principle the thesis of the confessional state. Otherwise, he should take his place next to the Catholic historians whose Americanist assumptions he so sharply criticizes.
W. Robert Aufill
Stillwater, OK
Michael Baxter replies:
Recalling a conversation we had last year better than I, Mr. Aufill complains that I hesitated to endorse in principle that the Catholic confessional state is the best form of government. I still hesitate. I distrust attempts to provide an account of “the state” in the abstract because such attempts legitimate what is in the name of what ought to be. I especially distrust such accounts in modernity because, as Alasdair MacIntyre has argued, the modern nation-state is a dangerous and unmanageable institution that often masquerades as an embodiment of community and a repository of sacred values. Faced with this situation, the Church does not need a theory of the state. What the Church needs is a description of the true character of the state and a set of practices to resist it. To designate the modern nation-state as an instrument by which to propagate the Christian faith is to imperil the Christian faith.
Mr. Aufill, if I read him correctly, is likely to reply that what he is proposing is nothing more than a normative principle to be accepted in theory (as a “thesis”) as a way to remind Catholics “that any political order is a ‘hypothesis’ in relation to the Kingdom” and thus to instill in them a critical perspective from which to engage the present political order in the United States. I am sympathetic with his aim, but I do not believe this to be a very promising strategy, for two reasons.
One, moral and religious formation is not achieved by means of a theory alone, especially a thoroughly disembodied theory such as that of “the confessional state,” which, as Mr. Aufill admits, is “not possible under present circumstances.” Two, the logic Mr. Aufill uses to explain our relation to the liberal state—that it is “a tolerable situation necessary in order to avoid greater evils but not a good thing in and of itself”—smacks of the kind of “lesser evil” logic that undercuts the integrity of moral action, including political moral action, whereby the intention and object must be ordered to the good. Indeed, given the structure of the argument put forth by Mr. Aufill, it is difficult to see what bearing a substantive account of the good has on politics “under present circumstances.” Here he could respond, I suppose, that the good provides guidance for critical, ad hoc engagement with the liberal state; in which case I would agree (this is a central claim in my article): but in order to function in this way, the good must be socially embodied in an actual community.
Rather than retrieve Bishop Doupanloup’s thesis/hypothesis construction in order to inform the sixty million Catholics in the United States that they live in a state of “hypothesis,” I suggest we set our sights on the good as set forth in the natural law and fulfilled and perfected in the supernatural life of Christ, and ask: what practices and institutions are necessary to sustain this form of life? The answer, as I see it, should come by way of descriptions of practice-based, ecclesial communities that exemplify a Christologically shaped politics. At the heart of such a politics is the belief that the peace Christ bestowed as a gift to this Church is best received by embodying that peace as a gift to the world.
But it is not appropriate to label this politics “pacifist,” for the case can be made that it is also represented in the just war tradition, which likewise stands as a challenge to the state-sponsored violence of modern war. Nor is it appropriate to trace the roots of this politics to “American sectarian Protestant radicalism,” for it originated long before Protestantism and it has taken root in places that do not fit the adjective “American” (which Mr. Aufill confines to the territorial boundaries of the United States), as becomes clear in light of the host of martyrs, saints, and disciples who embody it, including Polycarp of Smyrna, Martin of Tours, Benedict of Nursia, Francis of Assisi, Franz Jaggerstatter, Oscar Romero, Christian de Chergé and the other Trappist monks murdered in Algeria last year, to name but a few.
The significance of the Catholic Worker Movement in the context of the history of Catholicism in the United States is that it so clearly exemplifies this kind of Christologically shaped politics. History does not, of course, begin and end with the Catholic Worker. But history does begin and end with Jesus Christ, the Alpha and the Omega, and the Catholic Worker at its best has conformed its aims and purposes to this truth. In so doing, it has demonstrated a basic point that seems to have been lost to Mr. Aufill: that it is possible to avoid an Americanist accommodation to the liberal state without resurrecting the fantasy of the confessional state.
Tillich and Liberalism
Max Stackhouse should be commended for the virtue of constancy (“Humanism After Tillich,” April). He has, for some time now, swum against the theological current in calling attention to what he counts as the forgotten achievements of theological liberalism. And in the course of his writings about why liberal theology and liberal theologians ought not be forgotten, Stackhouse is always interesting, insightful, and almost plausible. For example, I should like to read more on how theology might exercise its prophetic responsibility to a society that must be simultaneously viewed as subordinate to the law of God as well as a dialectical partner whose God-given autonomy serves to “temper religion’s own temptations.”
Missing from Professor Stackhouse’s praise of Paul Tillich is the recognition that perhaps one reason why there are still theologians interested in Tillich is because we stopped following Tillich before there was nothing left of our theology. Stackhouse is correct that, for a time, orthodox theology accepted the sectarian option (which I think is better understood as finding a refuge in the Word and Sacraments of Christ’s Church) and started paying closer attention to Karl Barth’s early warnings about the consequences of liberalism. The reason why Prof. Stackhouse can still commend a liberal theologian is because liberal theology did not succeed in its self-destructive aim to transform itself in a form acceptable to secularism. Do we again need to remind ourselves that liberalism qua secularism is largely an agreement, based on the contradictory assertions of rationalism and empiricism, that belief in God and religion are to be marginalized in culture and politics?
In regards to Prof. Stackhouse’s attempt to resuscitate Tillich, I would not for a moment wish to discount Tillich’s profound courage in resisting Nazism before such resistance was fashionable. Nor does my argument need to suggest that Tillich’s theology, especially in his later years, was guided by anything but the most noble of intentions. Rather, I think that Prof. Stackhouse’s argument suffers from a selective amnesia in failing to reconcile his praise of Tillich’s project with the upshot of Tillich’s theology in his students and followers. If Tillich was a bridge between religious faith and secular unbelief, was not the traffic on this bridge mostly in the direction from faith to secular unbelief? There are two reasons that explain this historical reality.
First, the more that Tillich embraced existential categories in articulating his theology, the more his theology had to be distanced from the theological tradition and notions of teleology. Once theology is unable to articulate where it is coming from and where it is headed, it has subverted its ability to speak prophetically. Cut off from tradition and teleology one can no longer give adequate reasons for moral condemnations. For example, one may speak out prophetically against adultery by appealing to the theological tradition or by showing how sexual sins subvert the pilgrim’s progress toward the goal of faith. (I am not suggesting that Tillich’s sexual practices undermine his theology or I would have to withdraw my earlier praise of Barth.) When prophetic judgments are severed from the tradition or teleological context in which they make sense, they are no more than arbitrary preferences disguised as prophetic-sounding noises. As a matter of historical fact, liberal theology’s exercise of the prophetic responsibility turned out to be rather like a predictable echo of the “moral” judgments of secularized politicians and cultural leaders.
The second failure of liberalism is associated with the fact that, along with the Word that condemns the world, theology aims at commending this Word to the world. Yet after liberal theology had worked its wonders on Scripture, miracles, the life of Christ, and every doctrine central to the Christian confession, what was left to commend to the condemned world? If liberal theology would have succeeded, what creed would have remained to confess and what Church would have been left with which to confess this creed? While I am sure that Prof. Stackhouse is correct about the distorting effects of sectarianism, fundamentalism, and the return to premodernism, these things all name the way that orthodox theology and faithful Christians were able to survive the onslaught against the faith that went forth under the banner of liberalism and secularism....
D. K. Weber
Roberts, MT
Max Stackhouse replies:
I am grateful for the kind remarks about my work by Mr. Weber, and while my article is focused on a response to the Nietzschian challenge that Tillich’s work addresses, it does invite wider reflection about Tillich, and liberalism, as Mr. Weber suggests.
It may be true that Tillich led a number of people away from faith into the labyrinth of existentialism, and it may be that antinomian aspects of his work were a rationalization of his infidelities or had implications that, when applied to personal behavior, could lead to it. But antinomian accents are not unique to him in contemporary ethics, liberal or conservative. They have enjoyed a rather vigorous half-life among some celebrants of virtue theory and those postmodern Barthians whose view of “the freedom of God” excuses a moral situationalism.
But that may be a misreading of what Tillich is ultimately about, whatever his failures. What struck me and other seminarians about Tillich as a teacher was less the turn to a radical historicism than the fact that on the far side of it he saw an “onto-theological” “Ground of Being” (which, of course, everyone of us understood as God, and every post-foundationalist heir of existentialism today views as empty, dead, or in need of obliteration). In other words, he put the Nietzschian-existential-postmodern-anti-essentialist-deconstructionist drift of our times into a deeper and wider framework that finally constrained and relativized it.
It was this that made it possible for me, and a number of my classmates, to become, or to become again, Christians. The issues were tied up with the basic perception that many of us had then, and many more in the universities have now, that the choice is clear: one can be intellectually honest or one can be a believer, but one cannot be both. Tillich refuted the choice, acknowledging that much of tradition, religion, dogma, and our very mental images of God are social constructs, and that it does not help us face doubt by demanding confidence in them all the more earnestly. Tillich taught instead that there is good reason to struggle with and hold to the meanings behind these “constructs” because they also participated in and pointed to a reality that was not constructed.
Tillich sought to resurrect and restate the apologetic elements of theology that have been the companion to dogmatic elements until our time. He did, probably less well, what Augustine did in using Neoplatonism, Thomas did in adapting Aristotle, Luther did in drawing on Erasmus, Calvin did with aspects of Stoicism, and both Edwards and Leo XIII did with Locke. Each of these “uses” of “liberal humanism” enhanced what they did. Tillich draws on existentialist themes in his Systematic Theology, of course, but we surely must note that they are interpreted in the context of a work organized on a Trinitarian basis.
I have pressed this issue in part because I fear that fierce polemics against “liberalism” may prevent us from being discriminate about the varieties and kinds of liberal thought. After all, liberalism itself ranges from those who see the increase of freedom as a chief end of life, to those who argue for the relative independence of religious, sexual, intellectual, and economic life from state regulation, to those who recognize the truth and justice of universal principles other than religious ones.
While I do not think that any of these can be sustained over time without theological definition and guidance, as I argued, the impulses behind them may preserve theology from theocratic temptations or pious forms of ghetto-chatter (pietonics?). Blanket refusals to interact with humanistic thought prevent us from recognizing potential allies who could learn from and contribute to a faithful, enduring, and publicly compelling theological perspective. Such an attitude of refusal in itself would falsify the tradition, both because that is what much of the tradition is, and because it would deny that God’s grace can operate in and through channels that are unsure of grace or anxious about the very idea of God.
Religion & the French Revolution
When, at First Things’ invitation, I suggested that my book The Religious Origins of the French Revolution be given to Norman Ravitch of the University of California at Riverside for review (“Whig History Revisited,” February), it was with the full knowledge of his reservations concerning parts of the book’s thesis and with every intention of affording him an opportunity to state them publicly. Little did I expect that Professor Ravitch would take the occasion to dismiss my history as a “fairy tale” and choose to reopen barely healed confessional wounds with voyeuristic speculations about my “Protestantism” and its putative influence on the book.
The principal charge brought by Professor Ravitch against my book is that it is an instance of “whig history”; the bulk of his review is devoted to describing “whig history” in contrast to its opposite, presumably Tory history. As described by Professor Ravitch, “whig history” sees the Protestant Reformation of the sixteenth century as the origin of political liberty, freedom of thought, and economic individualism—everything “good” about modernity, in other words—while attributing to Catholicism the role of political absolutism, social hierarchy, and economic corporatism—everything left behind by the march of progress. The only substance to this gross caricature of my views is that the book indeed posits a loose connection between a heightened sense of divine transcendence typical of Calvinism and the secularization or “disenchantment” of the political world, including France’s sacral monarchy—a connection not for that matter denied by Ravitch—and an equal and opposite connection between a baroque sense of divine immanence typical of a certain Catholicism and the capacity to perceive that immanence in the political world, also including sacral monarchy. But that is about all, and it is not much.
The whole concept of “whig history,” it should be added, is a coinage by Herbert Butterfield who in his now classic essay on the subject specified that, in whig history, the historical heroes and villains in the religious and political conflicts that divided them are always fully conscious of the stakes in their struggles and fully intend either to promote progress toward modernity or regress in the name of the past. None of this has any bearing on my book. While it is true that the book considers the long-term “religious origins” of the French Revolution, and that its story begins with the religious-civil wars of the sixteenth century, Protestants drop out of this story after the very first chapter except to the extent that the threat that they once represented continued to shape the religious self-definition of the French monarchy and to haunt the Catholic imagination until and even beyond the French Revolution.
What takes the place of the conflict between Protestants and Catholics in the sixteenth century is a conflict internal to the French Catholic Church, that between Jansenists and Jesuits, in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. And far from leading directly either to the Revolution or to counterrevolution, these divisions give rise to politicized “parties” in the eighteenth century which in turn metamorphose into secularized “patriot” and “ministerial” parties and ideologies which for their part do not merge into revolutionary or counterrevolutionary ideologies before intersecting in quite unpredictable ways in the course of the collapse of the Old Regime and the coming of the Revolution. Not only are one-to-one causal connections and realization of long-range intentions entirely foreign to this plot, but the counterrevolutionary “conservatism” that is part of its denouement is as fully “modern” as its “liberal” counterpart.
Professor Ravitch can sustain his implausible accusation of “whig history” only by the further charge to the effect that my book has “protestantized” French Jansenists as part of an overall Protestant bias. To be sure, my book notes, along with just about every other one on the subject, that French Jansenists shared with Calvinists a starkly transcendent conception of God, a very profound sense of human sin, and a feeling of total dependence on divine grace. Yet like the St. Augustine from whom they derived these emphases, French Jansenists remain altogether Catholic in my book—so much so, indeed, that they also long retained certain characteristics of the militantly Catholic and anti-Protestant sixteenth-century Holy Union or League.
The only sense in which Jansenists occupy Protestant “space” in my book is in the (relatively noncontroversial) contention that a religious controversy about Jansenism within French Catholicism in the eighteenth century replayed some of the same issues that had separated Catholics from Protestants in the sixteenth century—and with all the more devastating effect for both Catholicism and the monarchy in that this second round occurred in a century of secular “enlightenment” and amidst the growing power of lay public opinion.
As to the book’s putatively pervasive Protestant bias, perhaps Professor Ravitch was misled by my conclusion’s qualified endorsement of the liberal nineteenth-century French historian Edgar Quinet’s judgment that a violent but failed French Revolution at the end of the eighteenth century was the price that France paid for having rejected the Protestant Reformation in the sixteenth century. Yet it is by no means necessary to accept Quinet’s prejudicial view of Catholicism to recognize, with him, that the failure of radical religious reform in France in Protestant form in the sixteenth century and in a more austere Catholic, or Jansenist, form in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries meant that it was left to a revolution that turned anti-Christian to undertake many of the reforms accomplished under more Christian auspices elsewhere and much earlier.
The result was not only that the Revolution failed to institute a stable political liberty—both Tocqueville’s and Quinet’s lament—in part precisely because of its lack of any fulcrum in the French religious conscience, but also a century and a half of ever more sterile conflict between a militantly anti-Christian republican (later socialist) left, and a state Catholic Church that chronically compromised itself in association with, first a royalist, then an anti-Semitic and quasi-fascist, right. If Professor Ravitch is really of the opinion that French Catholicism benefited from this chronic clash of ignorant armies by night, he is of course entitled to it, but it may perhaps be permitted, even for a Protestant, to doubt.
It should be obvious by now that this is a history written in a combination of ironic and tragic tropes; no more than ultramontane Catholics could Huguenots or Jansenists have derived much consolation from the way it turned out. How this history could have been so extravagantly misread by Professor Ravitch has, I suspect, more to do with his ideological commitments than mine. As for mine, the only clear political “lesson” contained in the book of which I am at least consciously aware is that it is unwise and in the long run even impolitic for any church or religious community to tie its fortunes very closely to a given state, much less a political party. Those among [First Things’ readers with ears to hear will hopefully do so.
Dale K. Van Kley
Calvin College
Grand Rapids, MI
Norman Ravitch replies:
I welcome Professor Van Kley’s moderate, respectful, and reasonable disagreements with my assessment of his book The Religious Origins of the French Revolution. His work is impressive and useful even if some of it appears to repeat certain historical fairy tales. In the final analysis Van Kley is upset because he suspects that I consider him part of what in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries was called the “international Calvinist conspiracy.” To this I do plead guilty.
The Virtue of Values
I heartily agree with Thomas D. Williams and his attempt to defend the concept of value against its conservative detractors (“Values, Virtues, and John Paul II,” April). Here are just a few points about English usage that support Father Williams and the rehabilitation of value.
Shakespeare speaks of value in Troilus and Cressida when he has Hector say (II, I)
But value dwells not in particular will;
It holds his estimate and dignity
As well wherein ‘tis precious of itself
As in the prizer.
No subjectivism of value here; value, far from being a function of someone’s arbitrary valuing, “dwells not in particular will” and is “precious of itself.” Recall Oscar Wilde’s famous definition of a cynic: the one who “knows the price of everything but the value of nothing.” The antithesis doesn’t work if value does not express an entirely objective dignity. And value expresses this naturally, organically, in full harmony with the genius of spoken English, which cannot be so easily eroded by artificial theories of the subjectivity of value.
Fr. Williams will find abundant support in the writings of C. S. Lewis, whose refutations of value subjectivism are unsurpassed. In The Abolition of Man, Lewis, who knew as well as anyone how to speak English with distinction and precision, argues “the doctrine of objective value.” Lewis could not say all that he wants to say in this book if he always had to say “virtue” instead of “value.”
By the way, the counterpart of value in other languages is just as capable of bearing the meaning of objective goodness as is value. Thus the German Wert is easily and naturally used in the most objective of senses, as in the radically anti-subjectivistic and anti-relativistic Wertphilosophie of Max Scheler. The same holds true for the Italian counterpart, valore, which at least since Dante often sets aside buono (from bonum, good) in favor of valore, as when he speaks of God as lo primo ed ineffabile Valore—no subjectivism of value would make any sense in such a theological context.
It is certain, then, that we do no violence to the English language in using value to express not relative or relational but absolute goodness; this is just one of the things it has meant for centuries, nor has the prevalence of subjectivistic theories been able to denature this expressive power of the word. And in no way does “value” lag behind “virtue,” or for that matter “good,” in the ability to express what is objectively, absolutely worthy. The expressive resources of the living language are not so easily undermined by the intellectual fads that come and go in the universities.
John F. Crosby
Franciscan University of Steubenville
Steubenville, OH
With reference to all this debate about whether we should place “virtues” over “values”: One cannot create a virtue for virtues are static, but one creates a value when he points to a virtue as a desirable trait. The virtuous point the way, and we adjust our malleable values accordingly. This is our calling as followers of Christ. The world suffers the fate of the laws of its creation: It winds down towards dissolution. So, first it destroys the virtuous, then those who value them....
Richard Stauch
Cypress, CA
For obvious institutional reasons, I am grateful to Thomas D. Williams for his vigorous defense of Pope John Paul II’s use of the term “values.” I can’t wait to tell the next person who wants to correct me on this subject: You don’t like it, take it up with the Pope.
Of course, I admit that, in 1987, when we were naming this organization, our thinking on this topic was at best hazy and intuitive. This lack of clarity is surely one reason why we are often criticized for using the word—sometimes from people who think that even “values” is preachy and presumptuous, other times from people who think that anyone who says “values” believes that all morality is subjective. Now, thanks to this fine essay, I am much surer of what we meant, or at least should have meant. I am also encouraged to hope that perhaps we were building better than we knew.
David Blankenhorn,
President, Institute for American Values
New York, NY
I applaud Thomas D. Williams’ article arguing in favor of rehabilitating Christian theological language. “Charity” is a perfect example of a wonderfully expressive word that has lost its former glory. When I teach, I am careful to explain to my students the full meaning of the word charity, in contrast to its currently emaciated self. Then I use it in my lectures and encourage my students to do so as well. Reviving “charity” helps to broaden and clarify our understanding of the ambiguous and multifaceted word “love.”
This rehabilitation of charity is important, however, because charity used to mean much more than it commonly does today. And what it meant (the love of God and our neighbors through God) is useful for theological discussions. “Values,” on the other hand, has no such illustrious history. Its use in connection to moral philosophy, as Williams mentions, begins with Nietzsche and Weber. Before that, the word “value” was used only to discuss merchandise and colors.
Rescued from its modern meaning, “values” seems to be of little use for theological discussions. Rather than a rehabilitation it would need to undergo a complete transformation of meaning in order to be useful. But that raises the question of why we need to transform “values” at all. Even transformed according to Williams’ suggestion, it does not seem to express anything more precisely than what is already expressable by “goods” (bona). Negatively, “values” also carries with it a subjective orientation as a result of its pedigree.
So, while I agree that the general project of rehabilitating Christian theological language is an important one, there seem to be better candidates available. “Faith,” “hope,” and “charity” seem like a good place to start.
David Burroughs
Boston College
Chestnut Hill, MA
...Thomas Williams’ argument about the prudence of using “values” language as an aspect of the Church’s “new evangelization” glosses over the occasions on which the term is used in ways that are unhelpful to the stated goals of the new evangelism. The official text of the Church’s documents (Latin) cannot use an equivalent to the term “values” whatever language the documents originated in or however many steps there are between language of original composition and the official Latin text. The term bona in the official text is fundamentally different from the term “values,” and language about truth and goodness is of a different order from language about “values.”...
Iain Benson
Center for Renewal
Ottawa, Canada
The Soul of Woman
In regard to “The Myth of Soulless Women” by Michael Nolan (April): that myth indeed did not die easily. In nineteenth-century America the Tennessee legislature formally debated and concluded that married women did not have free and independent souls and therefore had no property rights. This was, in fact, the legal position of women almost everywhere at that time, just as the women’s rights movement was beginning in the United States.
Amelia Bloomer, who had attended the 1848 Seneca Falls Convention but withheld her signature from its Declaration because of her doubt about whether women should vote, was so incensed by the Tennessee legislators that she wrote an editorial for her temperance journal, The Lily, in March 1849, which helped open the women’s rights discussion to a nationwide audience.
Wise men these, and worthy to be honored with seats in the halls of legislation in a Christian land. Women no souls! Then, of course, we are not accountable beings, and if not accountable to our Maker, then surely not to man...
We suppose the wise legislators consider the question settled beyond dispute, but we fear they will have some trouble with it yet. Although it may be an easy matter for them to arrive at such a conclusion, it will be quite another thing to make women believe it...
Amelia Bloomer herself, doubts now removed, went on to become president of the Iowa Woman Suffrage Society and an inspiration to suffragists throughout the country. So much for male logic about the nature of women’s souls!
Ruth B. Moynihan
Storrs, CT
(The writer is author of Second to None: A Documentary History of American Women.)
Of Canada and Cuba
As a recent Canadian subscriber to First Things, I was shocked to read Richard John Neuhaus’ diatribe against Canada (While We’re At It, April). Yes, Canadians are trading with Cuba, and are making a tidy profit from doing so. But what else should one expect from business entrepreneurs, given the U.S. embargo on trade with Cuba? Business is business, and American entrepreneurs would do the very same, given the opportunity.
Indeed, if Father Neuhaus would have listened to a recent CBC report, he would have discovered that despite the embargo, American entrepreneurs did $700 million worth of business with Cuba in the last year—secretly, of course! Sacrifice for the sake of moral principle, or sainthood, hardly befits the American (or the Canadian) entrepreneur, a point that could bear more exploration in First Things. Canadians are chastised for supporting a “brutal dictator.” But how many brutal dictators are enthusiastically supported by the U.S., and how many times is the often incoherent foreign policy of the U.S. governed by business interests?
And, yes, “the Canadian identity kit is almost emptied these days.” But I was offended by the tone of Fr. Neuhaus’ description of Canadian problems. Surely a more compassionate tone would be more in keeping with our common Christian identity. And a more compassionate tone would also be more appropriate than the inflammatory language of propaganda used to describe Cuba as a “morally sleazy” country. I thought First Things was a Christian journal.
You owe Canadians and Cubans an apology, Fr. Neuhaus.
Elmer J. Thiessen
Department of Philosophy
Medicine Hat College
Alberta, Canada
RJN replies:
I would assure Professor Thiessen that I do have compassion for Canada, but that might be taken as condescending. My objection was to the tone of moral superiority in some official Canadian statements about that country’s policy toward Cuba. And I don’t know why being Christian should preclude candid comment about the moral sleaze of the regime in Cuba.
The Catholic Church and China
I was pleased to read Richard John Neuhaus’ mention of China in While We’re At It (March), along with the quotation from the Pope’s recent statement and the apt analogy to Christians behind the Iron Curtain before the fall of the Soviet Union.
But I cannot help thinking that the Pope’s statement, while an important gesture and much better than nothing, is a bit mild. After all, telling the Chinese government that it has nothing to fear from Christians sounds rather like reassuring the trembling wolf about the ravening sheep.
As a Protestant, I may simply be unaware of something, and if so, I would sincerely like to be informed: When and where in the last few years has there been an open statement by a highly placed Roman Catholic official naming China and condemning and calling for an end to the Chinese government’s practices of forced abortion and post-birth infanticide? Preferably, such a statement would also contain words of comfort and support particularly for Chinese Christian mothers who are the other coerced victims of these abortions and for parents whose newborn children are slaughtered. I know that Evangelium Vitae talks in general about the evils of population control using abortion, but I found no explicit mention there of China.
Here is an irony: In the fall of 1995, Reader’s Digest—not a Catholic magazine by any stretch of the imagination—carried a story telling in detail about the horrifying (and routine) Chinese practice of ordering doctors to kill newborns who have no “birth license” by lethal injection into the soft spot of the head, even over the frantic pleas of their parents. Yet I have met devout, pro-life Catholics who know nothing about such infanticide, and who are almost incredibly ignorant about the ruthlessness of China’s forced abortion policy...
I have read that when John Paul II was just beginning his papacy, someone called out at one of his public appearances, “Remember the Church of Silence!” This phrase referred to the Church behind the Iron Curtain. To which the Pope responded, “It is not the Church of Silence any longer.” The implication was that, with the election of a Polish Pope, the Church of Silence had found a voice. Now, I fear, the Church in China has become the new Church of Silence, and who will speak for her?
Lydia McGrew
Kalamazoo, MI
RJM replies:
In an encyclical addressed to the universal Church such as Evangelium Vitae, there is no explicit reference to abortion in, say, the United States, but nobody can doubt the applicability of the condemnation to our country also. As for Catholic publications and statements by individual bishops, the Chinese outrages mentioned are addressed, but not nearly enough.
Novenas Past
In While We’re At It (April), the mention of the disappearance of holy days struck a responsive chord.
What ever happened to the “missions”? These were services during three days in Lent when a visiting missionary—invariably an accomplished orator with a Ciceronian sweep of syntax—would scare the stuffing out of us high schoolers with thundering threats of hellfire and eternal damnation if we did not mend our ways.
For weeks after the “mission,” lest we be guilty of mental dalliance with a shapely lass, we averted our gaze as the damsel tripped by. And, to make sure we had not harbored a wayward thought, we choked on a silent prayer.
What happened to the novenas? On thirteen Tuesdays preceding the feat of Saint Anthony of Padua, an empty seat could not be found in the church; as ushers at the services, we learned the knack of squeezing ten people in an eight-person pew.
The novena of Saint Francis Xavier always filled the church. One remembers the noon-day Mass when streams of the faithful flowed from the business district to the Jesuit church in the North End of Boston. The lunchtime Mass and abbreviated homily proved as inspirational and moving as a two-hour, trumpets-and-organ procession and incensed service.
And can one forget, ever, the short, sweet, simple prayer and talk and song in honor of Mary on the first days in May? We were college students and the novena was conducted by seniors of the college on the library steps and—although a priest could not be spared from his classroom duties—the impromptu novena was a touching, uplifting, and unforgettable footnote in our campus life.
Incidentally, on that same campus today, perhaps on those same library steps, a gay-lesbian organization of students gathers to demand status and office space.
The slow erosion of the traditions of the faith is reaping a strange harvest.
E. A. Siciliano
Professor Emeritus
Boston College
Newton Center, MA
Cancel My Subscription
During the past year First Things has sometimes delighted, often enlightened, and not infrequently prompted me to think hard. However, it has also vexed me more than it should have, particularly of late. I agree with the criticisms S. M. Hutchens and D. F. Wright made in their letters in the April issue. I was embarrassed and irritated by Richard John Neuhaus’ self-congratulatory apology for publishing Edward T. Oakes’ favorable review of a book by Martha Nussbaum.
First Things tries too hard to be all things. Diversity for its own sake or for the sake of retaining the good opinion of those who reject your underlying commitments does you no credit. Moreover, the sense of irresolution incident upon trying to tolerate too much engenders a defensive and meanspirited attitude toward criticism...
First Things has fallen short of the standard I expected of it, so I have asked your subscription department to cancel my subscription.
W. Dain Oliver
Newton Highlands, MA
Time is short, so I’ll be direct: FIRST THINGS needs you. And we need you by December 31 at 11:59 p.m., when the clock will strike zero. Give now at supportfirstthings.com.
First Things does not hesitate to call out what is bad. Today, there is much to call out. Yet our editors, authors, and readers like you share a greater purpose. And we are guided by a deeper, more enduring hope.
Your gift of $50, $100, or even $250 or more will bring this message of hope to many more people in the new year.
Make your gift now at supportfirstthings.com.
First Things needs you. I’m confident you’ll answer the call.